Laelius : Scipio :: Cicero : Pompey:
Cicero’s Continuing
Application of the Laelius/Scipio
Friendship in His Relations with Pompey
John H. Starks, Jr. (Randolph-Macon Woman's College)
Cicero’s famous closing to Fam. 5.7,
ShB3 (April 62 BCE) in which he asks to be Pompey’s confidant and advisor
(Laelius to Pompey’s Scipio) has often been assessed in its immediate context
as a vain miscue by Cicero or a vain rebuff by Pompey. And although Cicero’s
subsequent opinions of Pompey would ebb and flow with the varied fortunes
of the republic and of Pompey himself, his analogy to the friendship of
Laelius and Scipio became a canonical topos within his own literary career
and a personal reminder of his frequently recycled hopes for Pompey and
ultimately Pompey’s memory.
A.M. Ward (Princeton, diss., 1968) argues that the sage Poseidonius, an
inspiration and acquaintance of both Pompey and Cicero, most likely stirred
Cicero’s fascination with the Laelius/Scipio relationship, which he had not
alluded to earlier. Thus, Cicero, from his first reference to them, would
see this bond of renowned orator and soldier in broad rhetorical terms taught
by a noted philosopher, not simply as an historical exemplum. Thereafter,
Scipio and Laelius feature most prominently as interlocutors in the de
Re Publica, de Senectute,
and de Amicitia, with further
significant allusions in the de Legibus, Brutus, and de Officiis, several of which contain cross-references to each
other that further interweave the force of the allusion.
The de Re Publica and the de
Amicitia most prominently reveal Cicero’s
points of reference between the two sets of statesmen. The conclusion from
the de Re Publica giving primacy to the mixed Roman constitution (see
Asmis AJPh 2005) is however admittedly tempered by insistence on one-man
rule by a noble guardian in times of distress (Lintott Constitution 1999.224-5), a guardianship that Cicero felt would
be best managed by Pompey in the crises of 54-52 BCE (Att. 4.18; 8.3) while he was writing this work. On the other
side of the civil war, after disillusionment with Pompey’s failures, desertion
and murder, the Pompeians’ defeats in Spain and Africa, and Caesar’s increasing
dominance, Cicero turned to rhetoric in Brutus, praising Laelius,’ Scipio’s, Pompey’s, and his own
oratory to varying degrees. In 46-45, he defended various Pompeians (Marcellus,
Ligarius, Deiotarus) before Caesar increasing his praise for Pompey’s memory,
character, and conquests with each speech. Some time after Caesar’s assassination,
Cicero set his dialogue on friendship as an extended eulogy by Laelius
and friends after Scipio’s tragic death. The surprise and the intrigue
surrounding Scipio’s and Pompey’s rather unheroic deaths are somewhat parallel;
but even more important the de Amicitia itself
several times directly cites Laelius’ prior dialogue on government with
Scipio as recorded in the de Re Publica,
creating a cyclical interconnection of Cicero’s political philosophy with
his assessments of friendship as the synthesis in the concordia
ordinum and the senatorial republic. This work in some ways appears to have helped steel
Cicero for his final friendship obligation to Pompey when he reentered
active issue-advocacy in the senate and defended Pompey’s name, property,
honor, and legacy (especially his sometimes unpraiseworthy sons) against
Antony in Philippics 2, 5, and 13.
So in spite of Pompey’s reluctance to fully accept Cicero’s Laelius/Scipio
analogy, Cicero reciprocated nonetheless by usually being Laelius to Pompey’s
Scipio, especially in the philosophical works that envelope the last phases
of his career. His personal hesitations about Pompey’s ambivalence and hesitation
in his letters are overshadowed by a perceived public need for an experienced
man of accomplishments.